SAFELOGIC -- IMPLILOGIC -- TAUTOLOGIC

SAFELOGIC

Logic has two primary functions. One of them is to provide a kind of "safe" for guarding "truth", just as a real safe guards our valuables. When the methodology of Logic is properly used, any Truth put into it cannot leak out! On the other hand, we'll see below that, just as your real safe does not create your valuables, so Logic does not create Truth. However, this safeguarding is a precious function of language; and Logic warns us of other devices of language ("fallacies") which do leak Truth.
IMPLILOGIC
The other primary function of Logic is to show us when we know "something", then we may also know "something else". Logic does this via two connectives of implication known as "conditional" and "biconditional". We owe these to the ancient Greek philosophical cult known as "The Stoics", who were very concerned with language and its uses.

The conditional has the standard form of "if ____, then ___", where the blamks are filled in with a declarative form of language (a.k.a. proposition, assertion). (The "if __" part is labeled the precedent or sufficient part of the conditional; the "then __" part is labeled the consequent or part of the conditional.) To take a trite textbook example, "If it is raining (in the normal way), then the streets are wet (from the rain)".

(The caveats in quotes are there to bypass some smarty who says, "Maybe there's a big umbrella over the streets to keep them from getting wet.)

That conditional example is sometimes used in the most powerful device of Logic known by the Latin name of "modus ponens" (MP) of "tautology of asserting the precedent" (explanation of the latter phrase in another file).

			If it is raining, then the streets are wet.
			It is raining.
                        Therefore, the streets are wet.
Let "R" denote the statement, "It is raining.", and let "W" denote the statement, "The streets are wet." The conditional is usually denoted by a right-arrow, while conjunction ("and") is denoted by ampersand. So the above argument can be denoted: ((R Þ W) & R) Þ W.

The biconditional (a.k.a. equivalence) is of the form "If, and only if, ____, then ____". This means that the first statement implies the second statement, and the second statement implies the first statement, that is, the two statements are equivalent: say the "same thing". This is the best form for a definition, thus, "two sets are equipotent if, and only if, they have the same members".

The other useful function of the biconditional is to "lead us not into temptation (of saying something foolish)".) Example, with the biconditional denoted by a double arrow: x - 1 = 0 Û x ¹ 0. We can assert that linear algebraic equation if, and only if (iff), "x" is not zero. Why? Substitute zero in the equation to obtain:0 - 1 = 0 or -1 = 0. If you allow that, you "destroy" arithmetic, since very number equals every other number.

Logicians and mathematicians say, regarding "If A, then B", that precedent "A" denotes the sufficient part of the conditional, while consequent "B" denotes the necessary part. (In the Venn diagram, you see that the precedent circle or rectangle is inside the consequent one. It is sufficient to know that a point is within the inner structure to know it is inside the outer one; it is necessary but not sufficient to know a point is inside the outer structure, otherwise it cannot be in the inner structure.) In the biconditional, both statements are necessary and sufficient (the most desirable case, when we can attain it).

You glean some understanding of the difference between conditional and biconditional by Venn diagrams of logical arguments using them. A Venn diagram uses a rectangle for "The Universe of Discourse", and circles or smaller rectangles (perhaps overlapping or concentric) for statements. Here is the Venn diagram for that (conditional) MP about "raining":

                        ------------------------------------------
                        |                Universe                |
                        |   _________________________________    |
                        |   |                                |   |
                        |   |               W                |   |
                        |   |  ___________________________   |   |            
                        |   |  |                          |  |   |
                        |   |  |            R             |  |   |
                        |   |  |                          |  |   |
                        |   |  |__________________________|  |   |
                        |   |                                |   |
                        |   |________________________________|   |
                        |                                        |
                        |________________________________________|
The set of cases of raining is included in the set of cases of streets being wet, since the streets can be wet from a fireplug releasing water or for some other reason. (This Venn diagram represents MP in general: ((P Þ C) & P) Þ C, where P denotes precedent statement and C denotes consequent statement. The "direction" of the logic formula is reverse that in the Venn diagram. In the formula, the direction goes from presedent to consequent; in the Venn diagram, the precedent set (R) is inside the consequent set (W), that is, R Ì W. So, any point in the inner circle/rectangle (of R) is also in the outside circle/rectangle (W). Dig?)

Here is the Venn diagram for the "equipotent" definition, with "E" denoting "equipotence" and "S" denoting "same membership":

                         _________________________________________
                         |                                       |
                         |                                       |
                         |   _________________________________   |
                         |   |                                |  |
                         |   |  E                        S    |  |
                         |   |                                |  |
                         |   |________________________________|  |
                         |                                       |
                         |_______________________________________|
The set of "equipotent" cases is the set of "same membership". Dig?

Incidentally, one of the most common confusions is daily speech or in the literature is that involving "implying" and "infering". Example: "Are you infering that I'm stupid?" Should be, "Are you implying that I'm stupid?". The form "If it's raining, then the streets are wet" is implying. But MP (Modus Ponens) is an inference. Dig? You can imply with a single statement, but you need more than one statement to infer.


TAUTOLOGIC
I noted above that Logic cannot produce Truth, only preserve Truth inserted into a logical form. The criterion of logic is validity. I said above that modus ponens (MP) is the most useful argument in logic since it's enough to prove all of statement logic. But validities have a "flip side", as we now see.

The word "logic" derives from the ancient Greek word "logos" for "language". (The term "logorrhea" describes someone afflicted by "diarrhea of the mouth" -- say William Buckley or Joan Rivers.) And that indicates both the strength and the limitation of Logic. The canonical form of logic is "the tautology", meaning "sameness of language", since the prefix "tauto-" means "the same". As such, the term is often used pejoratively to accuse the speaker with redundancy.

This means that every validity in Logic is equivalent to a tautology such as "If it is raining, then it is raining". (Big hairy deal! as Garfield says.) So we need something more than Logic to aid our decision-making -- aid which we find in subsequent files.

Another limitation of standard logic is bivalency: any statement has one of two values, "True" or "False". We owe this to Chrisippus the Stoic. (It is incorrectly attributed to Aristotle (384-322BC), so that this is often mislabeled "Aristotlean logic".) And bivalency allows a nonconstructive method of proof known by the Latin label, "reductio ad absurdum" (reduction to an absurdity) -- a. k.a. prood by contradiction. If you cannot prove an argument directly, you assume its contradiction -- that it's not so -- then follow the consequences of this; if this leads to another contradiction, you argue that you have proven your original assertion. It is comparable to "double negative means positive"' or a two-pole light switch wherein two flips return the switch to its original state, whether OFF or ON.

One person who argued against "reductio" proofs was the Dutch mathematician, L. E. J. Brouwer (1881-1966). He questioned: If a criminal, in committing a crime succeeds in destroying the only evidence that could convict him, must we declare him innocent? Brouwer said, "No!", asking for a third judgment, "Not proven". Scottish jurisprudence has just such a verdict, and it was discussed in the trial in Lockerbee, Scotland, about the people killed by a bomb on a plane. During the discusssions about impeaching President Clinton, Pennsylvania Senator Spector suggested this form of verdict. A 1950 film, "Madeleine", sometimes seen on TV, directed by the great director, David Lean, ends with a "Not Proven" verdict. (Based on a true 19th century story, Madeleine is accused of poisoning her faithless lover by arsenic in a cup of chocolate. The Crown can't prove she actually put the arsenic in the drink, but the jury does not consider her innocent, so brought in a verdict of "Not Proven", sending Madeleine away "under a cloud of suspicion".) Regarding nonconstructiveness in mathematics, I published a fable.

Lawyers for gangsters have regularly taken advantage of our bivalent justice by forcing trials of their clients before the presecution is ready. Then, when insufficient evidence is cited, the jury finds the "accused" innocent, since it cannot find him guilty; and then he cannot be tried again because of "double jeopardy". This (along with other quandaries of decision-making) has motivated some logicians to introduce several forms of multi-valued logic into the literature.

Another limitation of Logic is that it obtains its bivalency by considering only the declarative form of speech -- excluding the interrogative, subjunctive, petitive forms. At another website, I describe a vectorlogic bypassing this limitation.

Still another crucial limitation of Logic (but little discussed) is that it is monotonic, meaning that it can increase in value or remain the same but cannot decrease in value. However, many have noted that this goes against history and experience. Information turns up that "take away some of the certainty we had for an argument". So, it is desirable to have a quasi-logical procedure which is nonmonotonic. And we shall discover this in another file.


In summary, Logic has its useful functions, so we incorrigibly do not change it. As with mathematics, we turn to another model -- in subsequent files of this present website.